Conversations on Morality

Discussions on the History of Conscience and Ethics

Recent Postings





(NAME)  G Riggs
(comments)
---------------------------------------------------------------------------
In fact, there seems to be some doubt whether or not Democritus was an
unequivocal, comprehensive atheist at all, in the sense generally meant
today.  Some early sources have him guardedly crediting the existence of
certain lesser divinities responsible for inspiring certain ideas, generating
dreams, etc.  He does appear -- inferentially -- skeptical of Deity as a
cosmic force responsible for ordering all that is, but that’s different from
being a throroughgoing nonbeliever in anything at all associated with
Divinity, something that Democritus may not really have been.

When it comes to that, even Leucippos’s stance is unclear, due to the
paucity of first-hand documentation regarding his atomic theories for the
universe.  We have him providing a materialistic explanation for the
cosmos itself, but never once is he quoted explicitly refuting (or
affirming) the notion of divinities, let alone providing any ethical
pronouncements in addition.  Since Democritus may have seen fit to
shoehorn ideas of lesser divinities into a strictly atomic, materialistic
structure for all that is, why not Leucippos his revered teacher?  Would
Democritus have really strayed so far from his teacher’s own take, both
on the cosmos and on divinities?  The evidence, in the end, remains
equivocal.

For unequivocal, comprehensive unbelief in Divinity as we mean it today,
two additional names from the fifth century B.C. emerge far more
frequently than either Leucippos or Democritus: Critias, judged by most
scholars as an exact contemporary of Democritus (most scholars place
their births at or around 460 B.C.), and Diagoras, a pupil of Democritus. 
Both these individuals appear to have been younger than Leucippos.

The evidence suggests that Diagoras was more overt than Leucippos in
rejecting the truth of religious belief. . . .but what religious belief?  Belief
in Divinity generally or in the traditional beliefs of the polytheistic
Athenians in particular?

According to some, Diagoras was a dithyrambic poet who had one of his
happy conceits stolen by a rival.  When the rival swore up and down that
the conceit had not been plagiarized but was his alone, Diagoras, fairly
theistic at the time, waited for the gods to punish his perjurious rival. 
When no comeuppance seemed forthcoming, Diagoras, outraged,
abruptly concluded that the gods were fictions and, among other things,
started scoffing at the Eleusinian Mysteries.  For this, he had to flee from
the law c. 415 B.C., and a price of one talent was put on his head, two
talents if brought in alive.  After fleeing Athens, he never returned.

The questions that arise concern, on the one hand, the nature of the few
fragments from his poetry that have, indeed, survived and, on the other,
certain contradictions regarding chronology.  All of the fragments that
survive show a deeply pious writer without even the mild skepticism of
his apparent teacher, Democritus, let alone the comprehensive skepticism
associated with Diagoras’s later transformation.  Conceding the bare
possibility that only his more pious writings would survive, this detail still
remains curious.  That a fair amount of time elapsed between his apostasy
and his effective banishment from Athens is shown in a brief reference in
Aristophanes’ *The* *Clouds* to Diagoras as a thoroughgoing atheist. 
Since *The* *Clouds* was premiered 423 B.C., we have, therefore, at
least eight years, 423 -415 B.C., where Diagoras was a free citizen
writing poetry in Athens -- and an acknowledged atheist.  It seems
fortuitous, then, that none of his verse from these eight years has come to
light -- the very years, moreover, when his notoriety was apparently at its
height, if we go by Aristophanes.

This is where chronology comes in.  One ambiguous source seems to
suggest that Diagoras was already on the scene c.465 B.C., about five
years before Democritus was even born.  So how likely is it that a
budding poet would take as his teacher a man at least five years younger
than himself?  Other circumstances surrounding Diagoras and Democritus
suggest that it’s impossible for Diagoras to have been older than his
teacher.  Apparently, so goes the story, Diagoras was sold in slavery in
his youth and Democritus generously offered to free him and rear him up
to manhood.  That certainly does not suggest a relationship of
contemporaries.  Furthermore, if Diagoras was already a presence in 465
B.C., that would suggest he was, in fact, born quite some while before,
making him an aged individual indeed by the time Athens put a price on
his head in 415 B.C.  

All of the foregoing is not entirely out of the question, but it does seem a
bit awkward.

To resolve all this, A. B. Drachmann, in *Atheism* *in* *Pagan*
*Antiquity*, has strongly suggested that Diagoras the poet and Diagoras
the pupil of Democritus are two entirely different individuals, the poet
having lived somewhat earlier than the atheist and pupil of Democritus. 
(It’s not unlikely they did overlap.)  Drachmann’s theory would certainly
explain the oddly pious nature (even by Democritus’s lights) of
Diagoras’s surviving fragments, the seemingly unlikely age of Diagoras
the “student” -- and the apparent fact that, aside from the one story
(apocryphal?) linking Diagoras the atheist to poetry and to an unhappy
rivalry with another writer, Diagoras the-notorious-sojourner-in-Athens is
never once associated with poetry, only with apostasy and with
Democritus.  I believe Drachmann may be right.

With all of this, Diagoras the atheist is never associated with
peer-bucking, autonomous ethical precepts as an adjunct to his unbelief. 
On the one hand, if he was not the poet, his probable inheritance from
Democritus of whatever pro forma ethical precepts he had becomes more
plausible than ever, precepts that Diagoras never, apparently, refined.  On
the other, if he was also the poet after all, and a very long-lived one at
that, his apostasy appears to have come out of a frustrated desire for
personal revenge, not from any wish to free his fellow citizens from a
perceived tyranny of thought.  This does not make Diagoras’s
promulgation of freethought very edifying or particularly ethical.

Since we do not have a precise exposition of Diagoras’s apostasy in his
own voice, this leaves Critias as the earliest extant formulator of an overt,
unequivocal, comprehensive atheistic stance left to posterity.  Since it
now seems likely that Diagoras the atheist was, in fact, of a younger
generation than Critias anyway, that may indeed make Critias’s own
formulation the first such exposition ever, not merely the first that
survives -- making the Critias fragment of incalculable historic
importance.  It was preserved, with one lacuna, in Section I of Sextus
Empiricus’s *Against* *the* *Physicists* and was lifted from Critias’s
satyr-play *Sisyphus*.  Since a satyr-play was frequently
tongue-in-cheek, it may be that this first exposition of comprehensive
nonbelief was intended to be tongue-in-cheek as well.  We cannot be
certain, since the context for the original speech is now lost. 
Nevertheless, whether intended seriously or not, its historical precedence
as, conceivably, the first formulation of its kind warrants its citation here
in full:


		“A time there was when anarchy did rule
		The lives of men, which then were like the beasts’,
		Enslaved to force.  Nor was there then reward
		For good men, nor for wicked punishment.
		Next, as I deem, did men establish laws
		For punishment, that Justice might be lord
		Of all mankind, and Insolence enchain’d.
		And whosoe’er did sin was penalized.
		Next, as the laws did hold men back from deeds
		Of open violence, but still such deeds
		Were done in secret, -- then, as I maintain,
		Some shrewd man first, a man in counsel wise,
		Discovered unto men the fear of Gods,
		Thereby to frighten sinners should they sin 
		E’en secretly in deed, or word, or thought.
		Hence was it that he brought in Deity,
		Telling how God enjoys an endless life,
		Hears with his mind and sees, and taketh thought
		And heeds things, and his nature is divine,
		So that he hearkens to men’s every word
		And has the power to see men’s every act.
		E’en if you plan in silence some ill deed,
		The Gods will surely mark it.  For in them
		Wisdom resides.  So, speaking words like these,
		Most cunning doctrine did he introduce,
		The truth concealing under speech untrue.
		The place he spoke of as the God’s abode
		Was that whereby he could affright men most, --
		The place from which, he knew, both terrors came
		And easements unto men of toilsome life --
		To wit the vault above, wherein do dwell
		The lightnings, he beheld, and awesome claps
		Of thunder, and the starry face of heaven,
		Fair-spangled by that cunning craftsman Time, --
		Whence, too, the meteor’s glowing mass doth speed
		And liquid rain descends upon the earth.
		Such were the fears wherewith he hedged men round,
		And so to God he gave a fitting home,
		By this his speech, and in a fitting place,
		And thus extinguished lawlessness by laws.”. . .
		- - - - - - - - - - - -[ lacuna ] - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - 
		. . .“Thus first did some man, as I deem, persuade
		Men to suppose a race of Gods exists.”


Whether or not Critias, in introducing atheism to humanity, did so as a
“satyr”ist or as a genuinely committed freethinker, his ethics are, sadly,
recorded for all time.  He was the chief oligarch among the Thirty Tyrants
at Athens, 404 - 403 B.C., instituting policies like abrogating the promise
to cobble a new Constitution, executing without trial statesmen like his
friend Theramenes when faced with advocacy for a moderate course
between oligarchy and democracy, and summarily executing without trial
dozens of private citizens as well, just to facilitate the use of their wealth
-- in the process thinning out the population in various pockets of the
surrounding countryside.  Even if we accept the notion that tyranny of
this sort was less frowned upon in ancient times than it would be today,
the Athenians of that era, in fact, reeling from such a Draconian reaction
to the world’s first democracy, came to regard the brief reign of the
Thirty Tyrants as a singularly cruel and bloodthirsty chapter by any
standards.

After sifting through these unsettling details, it’s somewhat reassuring for
an agnostic like myself to find that, at least, the first agnostic of all,
Protagoras the trailblazer for the Sophist school, did not wreak quite the
same havoc on fifth-century Athens as his confreres.  Active when Critias
and Diagoras were around, Protagoras espoused a relativistic doctrine for
everything.  Thus, in addition to maintaining that he neither knew the
existence of nor the non-existence of the Divine, he refrained from
espousing an ethical creed of his own, explicitly advocating that one must
abide scrupulously by the code of one’s homeland, no matter one’s
personal feelings or the radical differences from state to state. 
Pragmatism in all things was what this boiled down to.  Again, we find no
independent, autonomous ethical creed here, but, at least, there is no
explicitly vindictive path (like Diagoras?) nor an overwhelmingly
predatory one (like Critias).  Protagoras simply fits the general pattern,
noted above, of skepticism in tandem with non-independent moral
thinking.

Moving on to the fourth century B.C., we switch our attention to the
Cyrenaic school founded in the early fourth century by Aristippus the
Elder, a one-time pupil of Socrates.  One of Aristippus’s adherents later
that century was Theodorus, who pretty much adopted, with relatively
minor variations, the moderately hedonistic ethics of Aristippus. 
Theodorus is our next atheist, and, again unlike Leucippos, he was quite
explicit in his atheistic spin on what had been Aristippus’s somewhat
skeptical doctrine to begin with.  Unlike the possibly posing(?), merely
character-portraying(?), simply speech-writing(?) Critias, it’s abundantly clear
that Theodorus was a genuinely committed proponent of non-theism. 
Since, along with his more explicit nonbelief (unlike the less overt
Leucippos), he does not fashion an altogether new-minted moral
philosophy to go with his atheism, he fits the pattern suggested above of
pitting genuine independence from prevailing cosmic beliefs against
general acceptance and lack of scrutiny into the moral ways of his
immediate peers.


[The above comment posted to The Open Forum]



Date: Sun, 3 Jan 1999 21:49:49 -0800 (PST) (NAME) aggie (comments) This text reminds me of my feelings about current day television (and non-television)phony's that are sucking money and glory from an ignorant (or curious) herd of listeners and followers..--the Jim Baker's and Swaggart's, and Oral Roberts' of the world. This is my first exposure to the news group and the compouter. How wonderful it is to lives in a country where we have the freedom to examine, criticize and circulate the info. on the religious hucksters of old and current times. Thanks kindly. Aggie [The above comment posted to The Open Forum]
(NAME) GRiggs (comments) --------------------------------------------------------------------------- We can barely scratch the surface on this perplexing question. But that doesn't mean we shouldn't try. At the very least, to address it adequately, one should start by acknowledging the seeming contradictions within even the earliest strata related both to Confucian and Christian traditions. It is generally accepted that the earliest written chapters in *The* *Analects* *of* *Confucius* are nos. III through IX. More recent scholarship has restricted this even further to chapters IV - VIII. Even within these strict parameters, certain contradictions still emerge that leave the precise status of Confucius unclear. A few perplexing remarks of Confucius in chapter VII, in particular, may point in two directions. On the one hand, anecdotes 19, 27, and 33 suggest impatience with personal worship, while 22 could be taken as implying the opposite -- for some. Following are the apparent self-effacing disclaimers in 19, 27, and 33: VII: 19 " The Master said, 'I for my part am not one of those who have innate knowledge. I am simply one who loves the past and who is diligent in investigating it.' " VII: 27 " The Master said, 'There may well be those who can do without knowledge. But I for my part am certainly not one of them. To hear much, pick out what is good and follow it, to see much and take due note of it, is the lower of the two kinds of knowledge.' " VII: 33 " The Master said, 'As to being a Divine Sage or even a Good Man, far be it from me to make any such claim. As for unwearying effort to learn and unflagging patience in teaching others, those are merits that I do not hesitate to claim.' Kung-hsi Hua said, 'The trouble is that we disciples cannot learn!' " Some might square Confucius's apparent insistence, above, on his humble capacities against his assertion, below, made in the teeth of an apparent threat to him posed by a dangerous Minister of War in Sung, Huan T'ui: VII: 22 " The Master said, 'Heaven begat the power (*te*) that is in me. What have I to fear from such a one as Huan T'ui?' " I recognize that one could simply take this as an assertion that Confucius was armed with his own *te* (also translated as "virtue"). In itself, this is not necessarily a statement of any special properties to be worshipped. Nevertheless, one might see how a declaration of this sort would lead to worship of the kind rejected in anecdotes 19, 27, and 33. Similarly, when it comes to Jesus, if we confine ourselves strictly to the earliest stratum of Gospel writing embodied in the Vaticanus/Sinaiticus Gospel of Mark and the Q passages in Luke, possible contradictions still emerge that could also point in two directions. On the one hand, in Mark, 10:18, Jesus corrects a rich man who has just addressed him as "Good Master": Mark, 10:18 " And Jesus said unto him, 'Why callest thou me good? There is none good but one, that is, God.' " [appears as 11:21 in our Gospel sequence linked to this chapter] Squared against this simple statement of his mere humanity is Jesus' remarks in a Q passage in Luke: Luke, 10:22 " 'All things are delivered to me of my Father: and no man knoweth who the Son is, but the Father, and who the Father is, but the Son, and he to whom the Son will reveal him.' " [appears as 7:43 in our Gospel sequence linked to this chapter] Granted, this is a knotty passage. Many could dispute -- and have -- its precise meaning. Still, one can see how this might be taken (as could VII:22 for Confucius) as more of a warrent for special adulation than Jesus' more humble warning to the rich man in Mark, above. Naturally, I welcome other interpretations of all these passages from scholars more versed than I am in the intricacies of both New Testament and Confucian studies. I do believe, at the end of the day, that, however we interpret these various passages, the inference of contradictions in them taken by some others, whether correct or not, must be accepted as having led to contradictory traditions. --------------------------------------------------------------------------- [The above comment posted to The Open Forum]
(NAME) Alan Wild (comments) --------------------------------------------------------------------------- Thanks for compiling Q. I want to see what Jesus taught, not worship him as a man. Similarly with Confucious, words and ideas hold the importance a man is transient. Men should be remembered and thanked, surely, but not worshiped. Confucious and Jesus are worshipped as Gods. How can people pervert intent like this?! -Alan --------------------------------------------------------------------------- [The above comment posted to The Open Forum]
K.B. I am doing a report in English at my High School on morality as a result of religion, or vice versa. I would appreciate any feedback you may have on this topic. Thank you. G Riggs In a sense, all the exchanges on this site, particularly these three chapters concluding with this second half of Meslier's non-theist statement on social ethics, already deal with this fundamental question at some length. Summed up crudely, it resolves itself into a chicken-and-egg question. Did humanity's social urge for ethical comity and civic morality resolve itself into a presumption of deity and the metaphysical realm, or did an awareness of the metaphysical become transformed into an urgent sense of the Good? Stretching these questions even further, does the urge for morality come entirely from reason, with nothing of the Divine at all involved? It's possible that, to judge that adequately, a proper effort must be made to take stock of the true degree of probity, altruism, and thoughtfulness in humanity's first entirely autonomous non-theistic moral code, as Meslier developed it here in this concluding portion of his "morals" chapter, duly translated on this page. Others wishing to explore further the question of possible codependence of morality and religion are referred to a thought-provoking essay on ethics and religion by Jonathan Berg. It is anthologized in a book of essays on ethics edited by Peter Singer: *A* *Companion* *to* *Ethics* (Blackwell Companions to Philosophy), Paperback, Published 1993. Towards the end of Berg's essay, starting around page 529, the author deals directly with the question of the "causality" of ethics and religion's possible role in that. [The above comment posted to The Open Forum]
(NAME) G Riggs (comments) --------------------------------------------------------------------------- "I really don't look forward to scanning all ten volumes into the next century -)" Dec. 7, '98 UPDATE RE THE PRECEDING: From the modest follow-up I've done so far, it is not apparent that ancient Roman society recognized quite the same distinction that we do between the sacred and the secular. What still seems of critical importance here is Ulpian's own understanding of the Divine realm, as it related to the social dictates of his time. Was he, like Epicurus and Lucretius, a skeptic/ agnostic when it came to theistic worship, or did he believe such rites did indeed play a crucial role in social comity after all? This question becomes highly pertinent, since Knutzen, in fashioning a Conscientist, non-theistic creed, would appear (by accident or design) to have applied only to *theistic* moral tenets as the foundations for his moral, ethical code: Jesus in Luke, Paul in Romans, and Gregory of Nazianzus. Ulpian may be the odd man out. It is certainly striking how Knutzen has passed over any other more familiar classical thinkers and questioners in favor of the relatively obscure Ulpian. Was Ulpian a skeptical exception to Knutzen's theistic authorities, as the better-known Epicurus or Lucretius would have been? To my surprise, evidently not. Upon Alexander Severus's accession (in his minority) to power, Ulpian (as Alexander Severus's guardian) was placed at the head of a panel of sixteen ministers responsible for restoring some semblance of sanity to a realm wracked by Caracalla's abuses. And it was one of Ulpian's first measures to restore the theistic institutions, rites, and shrines relating to worship that had fallen into disrepute or been subverted by personal exploitation through Caracalla's excesses. This means that all four morality/ethics authorities cited by the atheist Knutzen (Jesus, Paul, Gregory Nazianzus, and now Ulpian) were veritable *institutional* theists, let alone *practicing* theists in their *private* lives. Knutzen, therefore, is far from generating an entirely autonomous code of moral action/ethics in tandem with his clearly path-breaking, "peer-bucking" non-theism. He is an original atheist with respect to his peers in academia, but not an original moralist, which remains our chief concern in these "Conversations." Looking over the available history on early atheists and morality, a whole slew of pathbreaking, peerbucking secularists throughout history demonstrate a thought-provoking trend: rarely, if ever, do they articulate a strikingly independent code of ethics to go with their occasionally quite courageous non-theism. Yes, plenty of atheists have been impeccably upstanding moralists, plenty have suffered heroically from having steadfastly abided by their unexceptionable ethical creed. But that creed, even when clearly altruistic and admirably self-forgetful, almost always stems from a code already established by others, not themselves. This is in marked contrast to more theistic figures like Socrates or Jesus, whose moral tenets are entirely original. Frankly, I was surprised by such a consistent pattern. It was certainly not what I was expecting. For example, the ancient Greek atomist Leucippos, arguably the first atheist, was, as Epicurus pointed out, "no philosopher." Leucippos would be regarded today as a straightforward physicist, though a primitive one. (He is still a formidable pathbreaker, though, in having been the first to intuit that all matter is made up of atoms.) It was, in fact, left to his pupil, Democritus, to put an ethical "spin" on Leucippos's findings. Thus, however upright Democritus's moral creed, and however valid his standing as a true "philosopher" (unlike Leucippos), Democritus, at the same time, was no independent atheist, having inherited his atomism from his "non-philosophical" teacher. Similarly, Straton of Lampsacus articulated an even more overt materialism than Leucippos had, explicitly ascribing various effects in physics and nature to entirely observable forces, rejecting any inference of the divine. And here we have a thoroughly upright individual and a formidable intellect who succeeded to the presidency of the Peripatos (the Peripatetic school in Athens) upon Theophrastus' death. But, beyond that, the prevailing pattern holds. As an inheritor of the Peripatetic tradition, Straton unquestioningly accepted (and why not?) the high-minded ethics of Socrates and Plato, without developing any original moral reflections of his own. When we jump ahead to the A.D. era, we do have a (possible) martyr to atheism in the finest, though harrowing, tradition of a Socrates or a Jesus: Vanini, whose horrifying execution in France during the early seventeenth century (his tongue was amputated and he was strangled and burned at the stake) is shrouded in contradictions. On the one hand, his clear rejection of extreme unction on the way to execution was described by at least one contemporary observer as being accompanied with Vanini's explicit disavowal of any adherence to either a god or a devil. On the other hand, Vanini's own extant writings only a few years prior to his execution show him still subscribing to the beliefs of Pietro Pomponazzi, a professor of the early sixteenth century whose ideas Vanini had always revered from youth. Pomponazzi was probably the first to put forward the concept of all religions being equally valid emanations of a true deity. In subscribing to this, Vanini's writings do not come off as atheistic in any way. But, we can wonder, Had Vanini changed his thinking by the time of his martyrdom? That is not clear. What is clear though is his continued acceptance of Pomponazzi's *moral* tenets, shown in Vanini's gallant statement on his way to execution that he wished to die "*en* *philosophe*" -- with equanimity. Pomponazzi's ethics followed Plato's and Aristotle's up to a point -- and Vanini was apparently faithful to Pomponazzi's new variation on Aristotle. Instead of viewing the Good Life as ultimately residing in contemplation, Pomponazzi viewed the Good Life as residing ultimately in moral action, and to this Vanini remained faithful. In this instance, where there are fewer historical contradictions, we clearly find Vanini unequivocally adopting, living, and even dying by an exalted moral code, though one not his very own. Once again, then, we have a possible non-theist who may be impeccably upright but without a truly original set of moral beliefs in tandem with his courageous apostasy. We can see that Knutzen, though not apparently a victim of some hideous punishment, parallels this same prevailing combination -- seen in so many others -- of original precedent-setting apostasy amongst even one's own peers with the adoption of perfectly upright moral tenets not necessarily one's own (in Knutzen's case, those of Jesus, Paul, Gregory Nazianzus, and Ulpian). This would seem to leave only one figure with the genuine distinction of having developed both a thoroughly original, courageous apostasy amongst his immediate peers and also a platform of equally independent moral action and ethics: Jean Meslier (see chapter immediately following.) At the outset of Meslier's posthumous tract, he explicitly rejects the veracity of any and all concepts relating to deity, maintaining that all theism is arrant superstition and that all reality is readily observable by the humblest mortals here on Earth. He maintains there is no dimension beyond the temporal, mortal one, and all lives exist strictly within the three-dimensional universe that we already know. In the excerpted chapter following, we give a translation of Meslier's call to moral action consequent to his initial declaration of non-belief. For the time being, I leave it to other readers to provide their own assessments as to the degree of probity, altruism, even-handedness and selflessness in Meslier's independent ideas on an ethical, moral society. --------------------------------------------------------------------------- [The above comment posted to The Open Forum]

Get Previous Postings

 

Post your comments to this page:

Your name or handle:

Please include a phrase to identify the part of the text you are commenting on. It is not necessary to quote a whole section of the text.

 

Conversations on Morality: Front Page